A BRIEF HISTORY
OF ARTIFICIAL
INTELLIGENCE

Chess Automaton

Stephanie Haack is director of communications for the Computer Museum in Boston.

The quest for artificial intelligence is as modern as the frontiers of computer science and as old as Antiquity. The concept of a "thinking machine" began as early as 2500 B.C., when the Egyptians looked to talking statues for mystical advice. Sitting in the Cairo Museum is a bust of one of these gods, Re-Harmakis, whose neck reveals the secret of his genius: an opening at the nape just big enough to hold a priest.
    Even Socrates sought the impartial arbitration of a "thinking machine." In 450 B.C. he told Euthypro, who in the name of piety was about to turn his father in for murder, "I want to know what is characteristic of piety ... that I may have it to turn to, and to use as a standard whereby to judge your actions and those of other men."
    Automata, the predecessors of today's robots, date back to ancient Egyptian figurines with movable limbs like those found in Tutankhamen's tomb. Much later, in the fifteenth century A.D., drumming bears and dancing figures on clocks were the favorite automata, and game players such as Wolfgang von Kempelen's Maezel Chess Automaton reigned in the eighteenth century. (Kempelen's automaton proved to be a fake; a legless master chess player was hidden inside.) It took the invention of the Analytical Engine by Charles Babbage in 1833 to make artificial intelligence a real possibility. Babbage's associate, Lady Lovelace, realized the profound potential of this analyzing machine and reassured the public that it could do nothing it was not programmed to do.
    Artificial intelligence (AI) as both a term and a science was coined 120 years later, after the operational digital computer had made its debut. In 1956 Allen Newell, J. C. Shaw and Herbert Simon introduced the first AI program, the Logic Theorist, to find the basic equations of logic as defined in Principia Mathematica by Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead. For one of the equations, Theorem 2.85, the Logic Theorist surpassed its inventors' expectations by finding a new and better proof.
    Suddenly we had a true "thinking machine"-one that knew more than its programmers.

chess player

The Dartmouth Conference
An eclectic array of academic and corporate scientists viewed the demonstration of the Logic Theorist at what became the Dartmouth Summer Research Project on Artificial Intelligence. The attendance list read like a present-day Who's Who in the field: John McCarthy, creator of the popular AI programming language LISP and director of Stanford University's Artificial Intelligence Laboratory; Marvin Minsky, leading AI researcher and Donner Professor of Science at M.I.T.; Claude Shannon, Nobel Prize-winning pioneer of information and AI theory, who was with Bell Laboratories.
    By the end of the two-month conference, artificial intelligence had found its niche. Thinking machines and automata were looked upon as antiquated technologies. Researchers' expectations were grandiose, their predictions fantastic. "Within ten years a digital computer will be the world's chess champion," Allen Newell said in 1957, "unless the rules bar it from competition."
    Isaac Asimov, writer, scholar and author of the Laws of Robotics, was among the wishful thinkers. Predicting that AI (for which he still used the term "cybernetics") would spark an intellectual revolution, in his foreword to Thinking by Machine by Pierre de Latil he wrote:

Cybernetics is not merely another branch of science. It is an intellectual revolution that rivals in importance the earlier Industrial Revolution. Is it possible that just as a machine can take over the routine functions of human muscle, another can take over the routine uses of human mind? Cybernetics answers, yes.

    Many people imagined that by the year 1984 computers would dominate our lives. Prof. N. W Thring envisioned a world with household robots, and B. F. Skinner forecast that teaching machines would be commonplace. Arthur L. Samuel, a Dartmouth conference attendee from IBM, suggested that computers would be capable of learning, conversing and translating language; he also predicted that computers would house our libraries and compose most of our music.

house robot

Getting Smarter
Artificial intelligence research has progressed considerably since the Dartmouth conference, but the ultimate AI system has yet to be invented. The ideal AI computer would be able to simulate every aspect of learning so that its responses would be indistinguishable from those of humans.
    Alan M. Turing, who as early as 1934 had theorized that machines could imitate thought, proposed a test for AI machines in his 1950 essay "Computing Machinery and Intelligence." The Turing Test calls for a panel of judges to review typed answers to any question that has been addressed to both a computer and a human. If the judges can make no distinctions between the two answers, the machine may be considered intelligent.
    It is 1984 as this is being written. A computer has yet to pass the Turing Test, and only a few of the grandiose predictions for artificial intelligence have been realized. Did Turing and other futurists expect too much of computers? Or do AI researchers just need more time to develop their sophisticated systems? John McCarthy and Marvin Minsky remain confident that it is just a matter of time before a solution evolves, although they disagree on what that solution might be. Even the most sophisticated programs still lack common sense. McCarthy, Minsky and other Al researchers are studying how to program in that elusive quality-common sense.
    McCarthy, who first suggested the term "artificial intelligence," says that after thirty years of research AI scholars still don't have a full picture of what knowledge and reasoning ability are involved in common sense. But according to McCarthy we don't have to know exactly how people reason in order to get machines to reason. McCarthy believes that a sophisticated programmed language of mathematical logic will eventually be capable of common-sense reasoning, whether or not it is exactly how people reason.
    Minsky argues that computers can't imitate the workings of the human mind through mathematical logic. He has developed the alternative approach of frame systems, in which one would record much more information than needed to solve a particular problem and then define which details are optional for each particular situation. For example, a frame for a bird could include feathers, wings, egg laying, flying and singing. In a biological context, flying and singing would be optional; feathers, wings and egg laying would not.
    The common-sense question remains academic. No current program based on mathematics or frame systems has common sense. What do machines think? To date, they think mostly what we ask them to.

CHECKMATE CHALLENGE
Designing a chess program is an awesome task. In a 1950 Scientific American article, Claude Shannon argued that only an artificial intelligence program could play computer chess. A computer that explored every possible move and countermove, he said, would have to store a total equal to 10 to the 120th power moves, and "a machine calculating one variation each millionth of a second would require over 10 to the 95th power years to decide on its first move." Shannon, the inventor of information theory, was one of the first to suggest that modern computers are capable of thinking-of performing nonnumerical tasks. It is this capability that lies at the base of all computerized chess games and of AI itself.
    Many of the first Al programs were programs that played bumbling but legal chess. In 1957 Alex Bernstein designed a program for the IBM 704 that played two amateur games. An alumnus of the Dartmouth Summer Research Project on Artificial Intelligence, Bernstein had been working on the chess system at the time of the conference.
    Then in 1958 Allen Newell, J. C. Shaw and Herbert Simon introduced a more sophisticated chess program. It still had some bugs, however, and was beaten in thirty-five moves by a ten-year-old beginner in its last official game played in 1960.
    Arthur L. Samuel of IBM, another Dartmouth conference alumnus, spent much of the fifties working on game-playing AI programs. His passion, checkers, proved a conquerable game, and by 1961 he had a program that could play at the master's level. Samuel believes that an equally good chess program would exist if anyone worked as long as he did on the design. Like most successful Al programs, Samuel's checkers player could learn. When it encountered a position for the second time, the program evaluated the results of its previous reaction in that situation before deciding on the next move.
    Surely the combined efforts spent on AI chess players equal or surpass Samuel's dedication to checkers, yet no program can consistently beat a world chess champion. Even backgammon, a less popular pursuit with AI programmers, has fared better than chess: the program BKG 9.8 actually won the 1979 world backgammon championship.
    This begs the question: why hasn't a world-class AI chess player been created? Claude Shannon may have answered that question twenty-five years ago when he suggested that AI programming would "require a different type of computer than any we have today. It is my feeling that this will be a computer whose natural operation is in terms of patterns, concepts, and vague similarities, rather than sequential operations on ten-digit numbers." If Shannon was wrong, M.I.T. professor Edward Fredkin stands to lose a bundle. Fredkin has offered $100,000 to the first computer to beat the world's grand master in chess.

S. H.


Return to Table of Contents | Previous Article | Next Article